Transcendental Arguments

A transcendental argument is a kind of deductive argument that appeals to the necessary conditions that make argumentation itself possible.

Transcendental arguments may have additional standards of justification that are more demanding than those of traditional deductive arguments.

The arguments

Typically, a transcendental argument starts from some proposition, and then makes the case that its truth or falsehood contradicts the necessary conditions for it to be possible to know, think or argue about it. Transcendental arguments are often used to refute skepticism. For example:

  1. Skepticism is the claim that knowledge is impossible.
  2. To argue that a proposition is true (in this case, skepticism) you need to say you know it to be true.
  3. Skepticism is false.

So-called progressive transcendental arguments begin with an apparently indubitable and universally accepted statement about people's experiences of the world, and use this to make substantive knowledge-claims about the world, e.g., that it is causally and spatiotemporally related. They start with what is left at the end of the skeptic's process of doubting.

Regressive transcendental arguments, on the other hand, begin at the same point as the skeptic, e.g., the fact that we have experience of a causal and spatiotemporal world, and show that certain notions are implicit in our conceptions of such experience. Regressive transcendental arguments are more conservative in that they do not purport to make substantive ontological claims about the world.

An example is used by Kant in his refutation of idealism. Idealists believe that objects have no existence independent of the mind. Briefly, Kant shows that:

  1. since idealists acknowledge that we have an inner mental life, and
  2. an inner life of self-awareness is bound up with the concepts of objects which are not inner, and which interact causally,
  3. We must have legitimate experience of outer objects which interact causally.

He has not established that outer objects exist, but only that the concept of them is legitimate, contrary to idealism.

Robert Lockie makes a transcendental argument for libertarian free will:

  1. Determinism is the claim that there is no free will.
  2. To argue that a proposition is true (in this case, determinism) you need to will to speak the truth.
  3. Determinism is false.

Not all use of transcendental arguments is intended to counter skepticism, however. The Dutch philosopher Herman Dooyeweerd used transcendental critique to establish the conditions that make a theoretical (or scientific) attitude of thought (not just the process of thinking, as in Kant) possible. In particular, he showed that theoretical thought is not independent (or neutral) of pre-commitments and relationships but are rather grounded in commitments, attitudes, and presuppositions that are "religious" in nature.

C.S. Lewis made transcendental arguments to prove the existence of God and refute naturalism.

Kant

It was Immanuel Kant who gave transcendental arguments their name and notoriety. It is open to controversy, though, whether his own transcendental arguments should be classified as progressive or regressive.

In the Critique of Pure Reason (1781) Kant developed one of philosophy's most famous transcendental arguments in 'The Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding'. In the 'Transcendental Aesthetic', Kant used transcendental arguments to show that sensory experiences would not be possible if we did not impose their spatial and temporal forms on them, making space and time "conditions of the possibility of experience".

Criticisms of transcendental arguments

As stated above, one of the main uses of transcendental arguments is to appeal to something that cannot be consistently denied to counter skeptics' arguments that we cannot know something about the nature of the world. One need not be a skeptic about those matters, however, to find transcendental arguments unpersuasive. There are a number of ways that one might deny that a given transcendental argument gives us knowledge of the world. The following responses may suit some versions and not others.

  • First, critics respond by claiming that the arguer cannot be sure that he or she is having particular experiences. That a person cannot be sure about the nature of his or her own experiences may initially seem bizarre. However, it may be claimed that the very act of thinking about or, even more, describing our experiences in words, involves interpreting them in ways that go beyond so-called 'pure' experience.
  • Second, skeptics object to the use of transcendental arguments to draw conclusions about the nature of the world by claiming that even if a person does know the nature of his or her experiences, that person cannot know that the reasoning from these experiences to conclusions about the world is accurate.
  • Lastly, critics have debated whether showing that we must think of the world in a certain way, given certain features of experience, is tantamount to showing that the world answers to that conception. Perhaps transcendental arguments show only the necessities of our cognitive apparatus rather than the realities of the world apart from us. This objection may amount to throwing doubt on whether transcendental arguments are ever more than merely "regressive".

See also

References

Bibliography

  • Brueckner, Anthony. " Transcendental Arguments I". Nous 17 (4): 551-575. and "Transcendental Arguments II". Nous 18 (2): 197-225.
  • Stapleford, Scott Kant's Transcendental Arguments: Disciplining Pure Reason - Continuum Publishing 2008 (ISBN 978-0-8264-9928-8 - hb)
  • Stern, Robert, ed.Transcendental Arguments: Problems and Prospect. Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Stroud, Barry. "Transcendental Arguments". Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968) 241-56.
  • Taylor, Charles. "The Validity of Transcendental Arguments". Reprinted in Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1955.

Tags:

Transcendental Arguments The argumentsTranscendental Arguments KantTranscendental Arguments Criticisms of transcendental argumentsTranscendental Arguments BibliographyTranscendental ArgumentsArgumentDeductive reasoningNecessity and sufficiencySubjunctive possibilityTheory of justification

🔥 Trending searches on Wiki English:

GhilliBrad MarchandClinton–Lewinsky scandalBillboard (magazine)Roman EmpireLiam NeesonHong KongNicola CoughlanThem (TV series)Leonardo DiCaprioAustraliaMartin SheenJayson TatumFascismKim Soo-hyunList of Marvel Cinematic Universe films2024 AFC Futsal Asian CupRonald ReaganGulf WarNetherlandsMalcolm XXXXX GoldHarvey WeinsteinAnti-Hero (song)List of James Bond filmsInvincible (TV series)C. S. LewisJason StathamJoaquin PhoenixNapoleonAndy (goose)XNXXPhilippinesArnold SchwarzeneggerJenifer LewisImmaculate (2024 film)Aparna DasKent State shootingsDeaths in 2024John Wayne GacyKate HudsonChessSachin TendulkarBlink TwiceStripchatLouis Mountbatten, 1st Earl Mountbatten of BurmaRusso-Ukrainian WarSandra OhVietnamTravis HeadGeorge SorosKim Ji-won (actress)YouTubeUnited StatesDeepak ParambolOttoman EmpireIndonesia national under-23 football teamBlack holeList of countries and dependencies by populationAndrew TateAndrew Scott (actor)Microsoft OfficeDead Boy Detectives (TV series)Bruno FernandesPassoverChanning TatumQueen VictoriaM. Night ShyamalanRussian invasion of UkraineAmy Coney BarrettAeroflot Flight 593CanvaWilliam Adams (pilot)RussiaBrad PittCarnation RevolutionMia Farrow🡆 More