Modus Tollens

In propositional logic, modus tollens (/ˈmoʊdəs ˈtɒlɛnz/) (MT), also known as modus tollendo tollens (Latin for method of removing by taking away) and denying the consequent, is a deductive argument form and a rule of inference.

Modus tollens is a mixed hypothetical syllogism that takes the form of "If P, then Q. Not Q. Therefore, not P." It is an application of the general truth that if a statement is true, then so is its contrapositive. The form shows that inference from P implies Q to the negation of Q implies the negation of P is a valid argument.

Modus tollens
Type
Field
Statement implies . is false. Therefore, must also be false.
Symbolic statement

The history of the inference rule modus tollens goes back to antiquity. The first to explicitly describe the argument form modus tollens was Theophrastus.

Modus tollens is closely related to modus ponens. There are two similar, but invalid, forms of argument: affirming the consequent and denying the antecedent. See also contraposition and proof by contrapositive.

Explanation

The form of a modus tollens argument is a mixed hypothetical syllogism, with two premises and a conclusion:

    If P, then Q.
    Not Q.
    Therefore, not P.

The first premise is a conditional ("if-then") claim, such as P implies Q. The second premise is an assertion that Q, the consequent of the conditional claim, is not the case. From these two premises it can be logically concluded that P, the antecedent of the conditional claim, is also not the case.

For example:

    If the dog detects an intruder, the dog will bark.
    The dog did not bark.
    Therefore, no intruder was detected by the dog.

Supposing that the premises are both true (the dog will bark if it detects an intruder, and does indeed not bark), it follows that no intruder has been detected. This is a valid argument since it is not possible for the conclusion to be false if the premises are true. (It is conceivable that there may have been an intruder that the dog did not detect, but that does not invalidate the argument; the first premise is "if the dog detects an intruder". The thing of importance is that the dog detects or does not detect an intruder, not whether there is one.)

Example 1:

    If I am the burglar, then I can crack a safe.
    I cannot crack a safe.
    Therefore, I am not the burglar.

Example 2:

    If Rex is a chicken, then he is a bird.
    Rex is not a bird.
    Therefore, Rex is not a chicken.

Relation to modus ponens

Every use of modus tollens can be converted to a use of modus ponens and one use of transposition to the premise which is a material implication. For example:

    If P, then Q. (premise – material implication)
    If not Q, then not P. (derived by transposition)
    Not Q . (premise)
    Therefore, not P. (derived by modus ponens)

Likewise, every use of modus ponens can be converted to a use of modus tollens and transposition.

Formal notation

The modus tollens rule can be stated formally as:

    Modus Tollens 

where Modus Tollens  stands for the statement "P implies Q". Modus Tollens  stands for "it is not the case that Q" (or in brief "not Q"). Then, whenever "Modus Tollens " and "Modus Tollens " each appear by themselves as a line of a proof, then "Modus Tollens " can validly be placed on a subsequent line.

The modus tollens rule may be written in sequent notation:

    Modus Tollens 

where Modus Tollens  is a metalogical symbol meaning that Modus Tollens  is a syntactic consequence of Modus Tollens  and Modus Tollens  in some logical system;

or as the statement of a functional tautology or theorem of propositional logic:

    Modus Tollens 

where Modus Tollens  and Modus Tollens  are propositions expressed in some formal system;

or including assumptions:

    Modus Tollens 

though since the rule does not change the set of assumptions, this is not strictly necessary.

More complex rewritings involving modus tollens are often seen, for instance in set theory:

    Modus Tollens 
    Modus Tollens 
    Modus Tollens 

("P is a subset of Q. x is not in Q. Therefore, x is not in P.")

Also in first-order predicate logic:

    Modus Tollens 
    Modus Tollens 
    Modus Tollens 

("For all x if x is P then x is Q. y is not Q. Therefore, y is not P.")

Strictly speaking these are not instances of modus tollens, but they may be derived from modus tollens using a few extra steps.

Justification via truth table

The validity of modus tollens can be clearly demonstrated through a truth table.

p q p → q
T T T
T F F
F T T
F F T

In instances of modus tollens we assume as premises that p → q is true and q is false. There is only one line of the truth table—the fourth line—which satisfies these two conditions. In this line, p is false. Therefore, in every instance in which p → q is true and q is false, p must also be false.

Formal proof

Via disjunctive syllogism

Step Proposition Derivation
1 Modus Tollens  Given
2 Modus Tollens  Given
3 Modus Tollens  Material implication (1)
4 Modus Tollens  Disjunctive syllogism (3,2)

Via reductio ad absurdum

Step Proposition Derivation
1 Modus Tollens  Given
2 Modus Tollens  Given
3 Modus Tollens  Assumption
4 Modus Tollens  Modus ponens (1,3)
5 Modus Tollens  Conjunction introduction (2,4)
6 Modus Tollens  Reductio ad absurdum (3,5)
7 Modus Tollens  Conditional introduction (2,6)

Via contraposition

Step Proposition Derivation
1 Modus Tollens  Given
2 Modus Tollens  Given
3 Modus Tollens  Contraposition (1)
4 Modus Tollens  Modus ponens (2,3)

Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks

Probability calculus

Modus tollens represents an instance of the law of total probability combined with Bayes' theorem expressed as:

Modus Tollens 

where the conditionals Modus Tollens  and Modus Tollens  are obtained with (the extended form of) Bayes' theorem expressed as:

Modus Tollens 
and
Modus Tollens 

In the equations above Modus Tollens  denotes the probability of Modus Tollens , and Modus Tollens  denotes the base rate (aka. prior probability) of Modus Tollens . The conditional probability Modus Tollens  generalizes the logical statement Modus Tollens , i.e. in addition to assigning TRUE or FALSE we can also assign any probability to the statement. Assume that Modus Tollens  is equivalent to Modus Tollens  being TRUE, and that Modus Tollens  is equivalent to Modus Tollens  being FALSE. It is then easy to see that Modus Tollens  when Modus Tollens  and Modus Tollens . This is because Modus Tollens  so that Modus Tollens  in the last equation. Therefore, the product terms in the first equation always have a zero factor so that Modus Tollens  which is equivalent to Modus Tollens  being FALSE. Hence, the law of total probability combined with Bayes' theorem represents a generalization of modus tollens.

Subjective logic

Modus tollens represents an instance of the abduction operator in subjective logic expressed as:

Modus Tollens 

where Modus Tollens  denotes the subjective opinion about Modus Tollens , and Modus Tollens  denotes a pair of binomial conditional opinions, as expressed by source Modus Tollens . The parameter Modus Tollens  denotes the base rate (aka. the prior probability) of Modus Tollens . The abduced marginal opinion on Modus Tollens  is denoted Modus Tollens . The conditional opinion Modus Tollens  generalizes the logical statement Modus Tollens , i.e. in addition to assigning TRUE or FALSE the source Modus Tollens  can assign any subjective opinion to the statement. The case where Modus Tollens  is an absolute TRUE opinion is equivalent to source Modus Tollens  saying that Modus Tollens  is TRUE, and the case where Modus Tollens  is an absolute FALSE opinion is equivalent to source Modus Tollens  saying that Modus Tollens  is FALSE. The abduction operator Modus Tollens  of subjective logic produces an absolute FALSE abduced opinion Modus Tollens  when the conditional opinion Modus Tollens  is absolute TRUE and the consequent opinion Modus Tollens  is absolute FALSE. Hence, subjective logic abduction represents a generalization of both modus tollens and of the Law of total probability combined with Bayes' theorem.

See also

Notes

Sources

Tags:

Modus Tollens ExplanationModus Tollens Relation to modus ponensModus Tollens Formal notationModus Tollens Justification via truth tableModus Tollens Formal proofModus Tollens Correspondence to other mathematical frameworksModus Tollens SourcesModus Tollens

🔥 Trending searches on Wiki English:

Travis KelceJerry SeinfeldGAZ SobolOpenAIReal Madrid CFIndiaJeremy Swayman69 (sex position)2024 United States presidential electionJamie DimonPoor Things (film)Winston ChurchillCatholic Church sexual abuse casesFranklin D. RooseveltSamuel AlitoAtomic bombings of Hiroshima and NagasakiBarry KeoghanList of Indian Premier League seasons and resultsChappell RoanIndira GandhiFallout 4WhatsAppPakistanErling HaalandLuka Dončić2026 FIFA World CupMarc-André LeclercUtsuro-buneCharlie Sheen2024 Indian general electionKung Fu Panda 4Them (TV series)William Adams (pilot)Opinion polling for the next United Kingdom general electionFlipkartThailandNazriya NazimAaron MotenDeadpool & WolverineStewart ButterfieldTokugawa Ieyasu2024 Premier League DartsElvis PresleyThe Age of AdalineEliot SumnerStellar BladeSwapnil SinghWestern SaharaBenjamin NetanyahuRobert KraftConan O'Brien2024 Croatian parliamentary electionMartin SheenC (programming language)Abigail (2024 film)Mahatma GandhiDaman, India2024 Indian general election in Bihar2024 Mutua Madrid Open – Men's singlesMiriam RiveraNational Hockey LeagueHeart (band)Michael DouglasSerena Williams2024 Andhra Pradesh Legislative Assembly electionNeha SharmaCeltics–Heat rivalryEmma StoneWikipediaIndian Super LeagueVasuki indicusBlink TwiceBritish Post Office scandalCassidy Hutchinson🡆 More