Logical Consequence

Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental concept in logic which describes the relationship between statements that hold true when one statement logically follows from one or more statements.

A valid logical argument is one in which the conclusion is entailed by the premises, because the conclusion is the consequence of the premises. The philosophical analysis of logical consequence involves the questions: In what sense does a conclusion follow from its premises? and What does it mean for a conclusion to be a consequence of premises? All of philosophical logic is meant to provide accounts of the nature of logical consequence and the nature of logical truth.

Logical consequence is necessary and formal, by way of examples that explain with formal proof and models of interpretation. A sentence is said to be a logical consequence of a set of sentences, for a given language, if and only if, using only logic (i.e., without regard to any personal interpretations of the sentences) the sentence must be true if every sentence in the set is true.

Logicians make precise accounts of logical consequence regarding a given language , either by constructing a deductive system for or by formal intended semantics for language . The Polish logician Alfred Tarski identified three features of an adequate characterization of entailment: (1) The logical consequence relation relies on the logical form of the sentences: (2) The relation is a priori, i.e., it can be determined with or without regard to empirical evidence (sense experience); and (3) The logical consequence relation has a modal component.

Formal accounts

The most widely prevailing view on how best to account for logical consequence is to appeal to formality. This is to say that whether statements follow from one another logically depends on the structure or logical form of the statements without regard to the contents of that form.

Syntactic accounts of logical consequence rely on schemes using inference rules. For instance, we can express the logical form of a valid argument as:

    All X are Y
    All Y are Z
    Therefore, all X are Z.

This argument is formally valid, because every instance of arguments constructed using this scheme is valid.

This is in contrast to an argument like "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew." Since this argument depends on the meanings of the words "brother", "son", and "nephew", the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew" is a so-called material consequence of "Fred is Mike's brother's son", not a formal consequence. A formal consequence must be true in all cases, however this is an incomplete definition of formal consequence, since even the argument "P is Q's brother's son, therefore P is Q's nephew" is valid in all cases, but is not a formal argument.

A priori property of logical consequence

If it is known that Logical Consequence  follows logically from Logical Consequence , then no information about the possible interpretations of Logical Consequence  or Logical Consequence  will affect that knowledge. Our knowledge that Logical Consequence  is a logical consequence of Logical Consequence  cannot be influenced by empirical knowledge. Deductively valid arguments can be known to be so without recourse to experience, so they must be knowable a priori. However, formality alone does not guarantee that logical consequence is not influenced by empirical knowledge. So the a priori property of logical consequence is considered to be independent of formality.

Proofs and models

The two prevailing techniques for providing accounts of logical consequence involve expressing the concept in terms of proofs and via models. The study of the syntactic consequence (of a logic) is called (its) proof theory whereas the study of (its) semantic consequence is called (its) model theory.

Syntactic consequence

A formula Logical Consequence  is a syntactic consequence within some formal system Logical Consequence  of a set Logical Consequence  of formulas if there is a formal proof in Logical Consequence  of Logical Consequence  from the set Logical Consequence . This is denoted Logical Consequence . The turnstile symbol Logical Consequence  was originally introduced by Frege in 1879, but its current use only dates back to Rosser and Kleene (1934–1935).

Syntactic consequence does not depend on any interpretation of the formal system.

Semantic consequence

A formula Logical Consequence  is a semantic consequence within some formal system Logical Consequence  of a set of statements Logical Consequence  if and only if there is no model Logical Consequence  in which all members of Logical Consequence  are true and Logical Consequence  is false. This is denoted Logical Consequence . Or, in other words, the set of the interpretations that make all members of Logical Consequence  true is a subset of the set of the interpretations that make Logical Consequence  true.

Modal accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea:

    Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  is true if and only if it is necessary that if all of the elements of Logical Consequence  are true, then Logical Consequence  is true.

Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently):

    Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  is true if and only if it is impossible for all of the elements of Logical Consequence  to be true and Logical Consequence  false.

Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of logical necessity and logical possibility. 'It is necessary that' is often expressed as a universal quantifier over possible worlds, so that the accounts above translate as:

    Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  is true if and only if there is no possible world at which all of the elements of Logical Consequence  are true and Logical Consequence  is false (untrue).

Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above:

    All frogs are green.
    Kermit is a frog.
    Therefore, Kermit is green.

The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can not imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green.

Modal-formal accounts of logical consequence combine the modal and formal accounts above, yielding variations on the following basic idea:

    Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  Logical Consequence  if and only if it is impossible for an argument with the same logical form as Logical Consequence /Logical Consequence  to have true premises and a false conclusion.

Warrant-based accounts

The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational", in that they all assume that the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from true premises to an untrue conclusion. As an alternative, some have proposed "warrant-preservational" accounts, according to which the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from justifiably assertible premises to a conclusion that is not justifiably assertible. This is (roughly) the account favored by intuitionists such as Michael Dummett.

Non-monotonic logical consequence

The accounts discussed above all yield monotonic consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if Logical Consequence  is a consequence of Logical Consequence , then Logical Consequence  is a consequence of any superset of Logical Consequence . It is also possible to specify non-monotonic consequence relations to capture the idea that, e.g., 'Tweety can fly' is a logical consequence of

    {Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird}

but not of

    {Birds can typically fly, Tweety is a bird, Tweety is a penguin}.

See also

Notes

Resources

Tags:

Logical Consequence Formal accountsLogical Consequence A priori property of logical consequenceLogical Consequence Proofs and modelsLogical Consequence Modal accountsLogical Consequence ResourcesLogical ConsequenceArgumentConceptConsequentLogicLogical truthPhilosophical analysisPhilosophical logicPremiseStatement (logic)Validity (logic)

🔥 Trending searches on Wiki English:

Ottoman EmpireZendayaLuke PerryWorld War IIThe SupremesList of countries by GDP (nominal) per capitaVirat KohliPat CumminsKaya ScodelarioMike TysonKetanji Brown JacksonGary GlitterPearl JamTurkey2024 ICC Men's T20 World CupSeptember 11 attacksDan Schneider2024 NFL draftList of largest citiesMS DhoniKepler's SupernovaBarry KeoghanUnited StatesYouTube PremiumShōgun (2024 miniseries)Michael DouglasWilliam Adams (pilot)Kelsey PlumMarilyn MonroeLily GladstoneBlackRockD. John SauerHTTP 404Survivor 46EarthBarack ObamaFIFA World CupThe Moody BluesDevin HaneyAparna DasCeltics–Heat rivalryState of PalestineList of hat stylesDhruv Rathee69 (sex position)Anthony Edwards (basketball)Jack NicholsonCrew (film)Emma RobertsStar WarsIndian Premier LeagueFascismLionel MessiDonald Payne Jr.Freddie MercuryJohn BlackthorneBrazilBarbie (film)Amber HeardSpainNimrod (comics)David BowieBob MarleyRichard Williams (tennis coach)Sonia SotomayorDream11Russo-Ukrainian WarAndré Villas-BoasTwitch (service)EnglandTerry A. AndersonGallipoli campaignNicola CoughlanThe Jinx (miniseries)The Office (American TV series)Andrew TateWalton GogginsInstagram🡆 More